Jump to content

Consciousness after death: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Ironrage (talk | contribs)
Ironrage (talk | contribs)
Line 29: Line 29:
A near-death experience (NDE) refers to a personal [[experience]] associated with impending [[death]], encompassing multiple possible sensations including detachment from the body, feelings of levitation, total serenity, security, warmth, the experience of absolute dissolution, and the presence of a light.<ref>Roberts, Glenn; Owen, John. (1988). ''The Near-Death Experience''. British Journal of Psychiatry 153: 607-617.</ref><ref name=Britton&Bootzin>Britton, Willoughby B. and Richard R. Bootzin. (2004). ''Near-Death Experiences and the Temporal Lobe''. Psychological Science. Vol. 15, No. 4. pp. 254-258.</ref>
A near-death experience (NDE) refers to a personal [[experience]] associated with impending [[death]], encompassing multiple possible sensations including detachment from the body, feelings of levitation, total serenity, security, warmth, the experience of absolute dissolution, and the presence of a light.<ref>Roberts, Glenn; Owen, John. (1988). ''The Near-Death Experience''. British Journal of Psychiatry 153: 607-617.</ref><ref name=Britton&Bootzin>Britton, Willoughby B. and Richard R. Bootzin. (2004). ''Near-Death Experiences and the Temporal Lobe''. Psychological Science. Vol. 15, No. 4. pp. 254-258.</ref>


Explanatory models for the NDE can be divided into several broad categories, including [[psychology|psychological]], [[physiology|physiological]], and [[transcendence (philosophy)|transcendental]] explanations.<ref>Linda J. Griffith. "[http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2790400/ Near-Death Experiences and Psychotherapy]" (2009).</ref><ref>Mauro, James. Bright lights, big mystery. Psychology Today, July 1992</ref><ref>Vanhaudenhuyse, A; Thonnard, M; Laureys, S. "[http://www.coma.ulg.ac.be/papers/vs/vanhaudenhuyse_NDE2010.pdf Towards a Neuro-scientific Explanation of Near-death Experiences?]" (2009).</ref> Research from neuroscience considers the NDE to be a hallucination caused by various physiological and psychological factors,<ref>Olaf Blanke, Sebastian Dieguez. "[http://infoscience.epfl.ch/record/154824/files/2009_Blanke_TNC%28chap%29_leaving%20body%20and%20life%20behind%20-%20obe%20and%20nde.pdf Leaving Body and Life Behind: Out-of-Body and Near-Death Experience]" (2009).</ref> while some NDE researchers in the field of [[near-death studies]] advocate for a transcendental explanation.<ref name="horizonresearch.org">Sam Parnia, Peter Fenwick. "[http://www.horizonresearch.org/Uploads/resusrv.pdf Near death experiences in cardiac arrest: visions of a dying brain or visions of a new science of consciousness]" (2001).</ref><ref name="www-new1.heacademy.ac.uk">{{cite book|last1=Murray|first1=Craig D.|title=Psychological Scientific Perspectives on Out-of-Body and Near-Death Experiences|date=2009|publisher=Nova Science Publishers|location=New York|isbn=978-1-60741-705-7|pages=187-203|accessdate=13 December 2014}}</ref>
Explanatory models for the NDE can be divided into several broad categories, including [[psychology|psychological]], [[physiology|physiological]], and [[transcendence (philosophy)|transcendental]] explanations.<ref>Linda J. Griffith. "[http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2790400/ Near-Death Experiences and Psychotherapy]" (2009).</ref><ref>Mauro, James. Bright lights, big mystery. Psychology Today, July 1992</ref><ref>Vanhaudenhuyse, A; Thonnard, M; Laureys, S. "[http://www.coma.ulg.ac.be/papers/vs/vanhaudenhuyse_NDE2010.pdf Towards a Neuro-scientific Explanation of Near-death Experiences?]" (2009).</ref> Research from neuroscience considers the NDE to be a hallucination caused by various physiological and psychological factors,<ref>Olaf Blanke, Sebastian Dieguez. "[http://infoscience.epfl.ch/record/154824/files/2009_Blanke_TNC%28chap%29_leaving%20body%20and%20life%20behind%20-%20obe%20and%20nde.pdf Leaving Body and Life Behind: Out-of-Body and Near-Death Experience]" (2009).</ref> while some NDE researchers in the field of [[near-death studies]], notably [[Pim van Lommel]]<ref name=lommel2>van Lommel P, van Wees R, Meyers V, Elfferich I. (2001) "Near-Death Experience in Survivors of Cardiac Arrest: A prospective Study in the Netherlands," ''The Lancet'', December 15; 358 (9298):2039-45. Table 2.</ref>, [[Sam Parnia]], [[Peter Fenwick (neuropsychologist)|Peter Fenwick]]<ref>Sam Parnia, Peter Fenwick. "[http://www.horizonresearch.org/Uploads/resusrv.pdf Near death experiences in cardiac arrest: visions of a dying brain or visions of a new science of consciousness]" (2001).</ref> and [[Bruce Greyson]]<ref>Greyson, B. (2003) Incidence and correlates of near-death experiences in a cardiac care unit. Gen. Hosp. Psychiat., 25: 269–276.</ref> have argued that the NDE cannot be adequately explained by physiological and psychological causes and that the experience poses a major challenge to current [[materialism|materialistic]] thinking regarding the [[mind–body problem|relationship between consciousness and the brain]]. The major premise behind the argument that NDEs present such a challenge is that the experience represents a case of a heightened lucid consciousness happening while the brain either no longer functions or while being to severely impaired to support such a lucid consciousness.

According to [[neuroscientist]] Jason J. Braithwaite,

{{quote|Where neuroscience and the paranormalist part intellectual company is primarily over the existence of objective cases where lucid experience occurs in the co-presence of objective, verifiable evidence of total and complete brain inactivity or brain activity insufficient to support consciousness. In many ways this gets to the crux of the theoretical divide between neuroscientific accounts of the NDE and those ideas consistent with paranormal/dualistic interpretations of the NDE. The paranormalist makes a number of sweeping assumptions about the existence of certain evidence, about the brain, about psychology, and then from this muddy premise, argues that certain observations demand explanation from mainstream science. However, the neuroscientist does not accept that these cases, as presented by paranormalists, have ever really been established or actually represent the type of evidence the paranormalist presumes. As such, the need for this type of explanation becomes redundant. The theoretical divide then can be seen as one of sufficiency, where the paranormalist thinks a sufficient case has been made to demand explanation, and the neuroscientist views the case to be insufficient to warrant one."<ref>Dr. Jason J Braithwaite, Hayley Dewe MSc. "[http://www.academia.edu/10060970/Occams_Chainsaw_Neuroscientific_Nails_in_the_coffin_of_dualist_notions_of_the_Near-death_experience_NDE_ Occam's Chainsaw: Neuroscientific Nails in the Coffin of Dualist Notions of the Near-death Experience (NDE)]" (2014).</ref>}}

The "heightened lucid consciousness" of NDErs is according to Braithwaite<ref>Dr. Jason J Braithwaite. "[http://www.academia.edu/574245/Towards_a_Cognitive_Neuroscience_of_the_Dying_Brain Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of the Dying Brain]" (2008).</ref> compatible with the predictions of the dying-brain hypothesis, "...the dying-brain hypothesis predicts that more vivid, profound, and meaningful NDEs are likely to be associated with greater degrees of disinhibition. Thus, NDEs reported when people truly are nearer to death (and hence the level of disinhibition would conceivably be greater), should be more vivid, profound, detailed and meaningful, relative to those reported when people only believed themselves to be so. This is exactly what has been found."

In contrast to the hypothesis that NDEs occur during the supposed period of no brain activity or brain activity insufficient to support consciousness, Braithwaite (2014), as well as [[psychologist]] [[Chris French]]<ref>French, Christopher C. "[http://research.gold.ac.uk/420/ Near-death experiences in cardiac arrest survivors ]" (2005).</ref> argued that the NDE could easily have occurred well before brain activity ceased, or well after during recovery. Parnia and Fenwick (2001) had rejected the idea that the NDE may have occurred just prior to or just after the loss of consciousness. They argued that LOC happens too quickly and that events that occur just prior (or just after) would not be expected to be recalled, and that the period of recovery is characterized by [[delirium]] and not by the lucid consciousness reported by NDErs. In a summary of these arguments, Braithwaite (2014) concluded that "all claims about the phenomenology being different between NDEs and syncope, or the time periods in cases of cardiac arrest being 'too quick' are irrelevant as neither pertain to the actual arguments from the syncopal model. As a consequence, these specific dualist arguments against syncope as a comparative
model of NDEs can be legitimately ignored."

Parnia and Fenwick (2001) also argued that the occurrence of [[anecdotal evidence|anecdotal reports]] of patients being able to see and recall detailed events occurring during the cardiac arrest that are afterwards verified by hospital staff supports the argument that such perception sometimes do occur during periods of clinical death. NDE researcher Janice Miner Holden found 107 such anecdotal reports in the NDE literature as of 2009, out of which approximately 91% were accurate.<ref>Holden, J.M. (2009) Veridical perception in near-death experiences. In The Handbook of Near-Death Experiences (Holden, J.M. et al., eds), pp. 185–211.</ref>

According to French (2005) and [[Susan Blackmore|Blackmore]] (1993), when serious attempts at corroboration are attempted, the evidence often turns out to be nowhere near as impressive as it initially appeared.<ref>Blackmore, S.J. (1993) Dying to Live: Science and the Near-Death Experience. Grafton, London.</ref> And such cases can possibly (since they had not been ruled out) be accounted for in terms of non-paranormal factors including, "information available at the time, prior knowledge, fantasy or dreams, lucky guesses, and information from the remaining senses. Then there is selective memory for correct details, incorporation of details learned between the end of the NDE and giving an account of it, and the tendency to tell a good story.”<ref>Blackmore, S.J. (1996b). Out-of-body experiences. In G. Stein (ed.), The encyclopedia of the paranormal. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. Pp. 471-483.</ref>

NDE researchers have also been criticized by scientists of placing undue confidence in EEG measures. French (2005) and Braithwaite (2008, 2014) claimed that survivalists generally appear to assume that a flat EEG is indicative of total brain inactivity. Even assuming that NDEs actually occur during such periods, the assumption that isoelectric surface EEG recordings are always indicative of total brain inactivity is according to Braithwaite and French wrong. Braithwaite noted that "unless surgically implanted into the brain directly, the EEG principally measures surface cortical activity. The waveforms seen in cortical EEG are largely regarded to come from the synchronistic firing of cortical pyramidal neurons. As such, it is entirely conceivable that deep sub-cortical brain structures could be firing, and even in seizure, in the absence of any cortical signs of this activity."<ref name="Braithwaite 2008"/><ref>Paolin, A., Manuali, A., Di Paola, F., Boccaletto, F., Caputo, P., Zanata, R., Bardin, G.P. and Simini, G. (1995). ''Reliability in diagnosis of brain death''. Intens Care Med 21: 657–662.</ref><ref>Bardy, A. H. (2002). ''Near-death experiences [letter]''. Lancet 359: 2116.</ref>

According to French (2005) future research in the near-death experience should focus on devising ways to distinguish between the two main hypotheses relating to when the NDE is occurring.<ref name="French2005"/> If it really is occurring when some NDE researchers claim that it is, during a period of flat EEG with no cortical activity, then modern neuroscience would require serious revision.<ref name="French2005"/> This would also be the case if the OBE, either within the NDE or not, could be shown to be veridical. Attempts to test the veridicality of OBEs using hidden targets (e.g., Parnia and Fenwick (2001) should be welcomed.<ref name="French2005"/>


==See also==
==See also==

Revision as of 13:11, 3 May 2015

Consciousness after death is a common theme in society and culture in the context of life after death. Scientific research has established that the mind and normal waking consciousness are closely connected with the physiological functioning of the brain, the cessation of which defines brain death. However, many people believe in some form of life after death, which is a feature of many religions.

Neuroscience

Neuroscience is a large interdisciplinary field founded on the premise that all of behavior and all of the cognitive processes that constitute the mind have their origin in the structure and function of the nervous system, especially in the brain. According to this view, the mind can be regarded as a set of operations carried out by the brain.[1][2][3][4][5]

There are multiple lines of evidence that support this view. They are here briefly summarized along with some examples.

  • Neuroanatomical correlates: In the field of neuroimaging, neuroscientists can use various functional neuroimaging methods to measure an aspect of brain function that correlates with a particular mental state or process.
  • Experimental manipulations: Neuroimaging (correlational) studies cannot determine whether neural activity plays a causal role in the occurrence of mental processes (correlation does not imply causation) and they cannot determine if the neural activity is either necessary and sufficient for such processes to occur. Identification of causation and necessary and sufficient conditions requires explicit experimental manipulation of that activity. If manipulation of brain activity changes consciousness, then a causal role for that brain activity can be inferred.[6][7] Two of the most common types of manipulation experiments are loss-of-function and gain-of-function experiments. In a loss-of-function (also called "necessity") experiment, a part of the nervous system is diminished or removed in an attempt to determine if it is necessary for a certain process to occur, and in a gain-of-function (also called "sufficiency") experiment, an aspect of the nervous system is increased relative to normal.[8] Manipulations of brain activity can be performed in several ways:
Pharmacological manipulation using various drugs which alter neural activity by interfering with neurotransmission, resulting in alterations in perception, mood, consciousness, cognition, and behavior. Psychoactive drugs are divided into different groups according to their pharmacological effects; euphoriants which tend to induce feelings of euphoria, stimulants that induce temporary improvements in either mental or physical functions, depressants that depress or reduce arousal or stimulation and hallucinogens which can cause hallucinations, perception anomalies, and other substantial subjective changes in thoughts, emotion, and consciousness.
Electrical and magnetical stimulations using various electrical methods and techniques like transcranial magnetic stimulation. In a comprehensive review of electrical brain stimulation (EBS) results obtained from the last 100 years neuroscientist Aslihan Selimbeyoglu and neurologist Josef Parvizi compiled a list of many different subjective experiential phenomena and behavioral changes that can be caused by electrical stimulation of the cerebral cortex or subcortical nuclei in awake and conscious human subjects.[9]
Optogenetic manipulation where light is used to control neurons which have been genetically sensitised to light.

Death

Death was once defined as the cessation of heartbeat (cardiac arrest) and of breathing, but the development of CPR and prompt defibrillation have rendered that definition inadequate because breathing and heartbeat can sometimes be restarted. Events which were causally linked to death in the past no longer kill in all circumstances; without a functioning heart or lungs, life can sometimes be sustained with a combination of life support devices, organ transplants and artificial pacemakers.

Today, where a definition of the moment of death is required, doctors and coroners usually turn to "brain death" or "biological death" to define a person as being dead; brain death being defined as the complete and irreversible loss of brain function (including involuntary activity necessary to sustain life).[15][16][17][18]

According to the current neuroscientific view, consciousness fails to survive brain death and ceases to exist.[19][20]

Near-death experiences (NDEs)

A near-death experience (NDE) refers to a personal experience associated with impending death, encompassing multiple possible sensations including detachment from the body, feelings of levitation, total serenity, security, warmth, the experience of absolute dissolution, and the presence of a light.[21][22]

Explanatory models for the NDE can be divided into several broad categories, including psychological, physiological, and transcendental explanations.[23][24][25] Research from neuroscience considers the NDE to be a hallucination caused by various physiological and psychological factors,[26] while some NDE researchers in the field of near-death studies, notably Pim van Lommel[27], Sam Parnia, Peter Fenwick[28] and Bruce Greyson[29] have argued that the NDE cannot be adequately explained by physiological and psychological causes and that the experience poses a major challenge to current materialistic thinking regarding the relationship between consciousness and the brain. The major premise behind the argument that NDEs present such a challenge is that the experience represents a case of a heightened lucid consciousness happening while the brain either no longer functions or while being to severely impaired to support such a lucid consciousness.

According to neuroscientist Jason J. Braithwaite,

Where neuroscience and the paranormalist part intellectual company is primarily over the existence of objective cases where lucid experience occurs in the co-presence of objective, verifiable evidence of total and complete brain inactivity or brain activity insufficient to support consciousness. In many ways this gets to the crux of the theoretical divide between neuroscientific accounts of the NDE and those ideas consistent with paranormal/dualistic interpretations of the NDE. The paranormalist makes a number of sweeping assumptions about the existence of certain evidence, about the brain, about psychology, and then from this muddy premise, argues that certain observations demand explanation from mainstream science. However, the neuroscientist does not accept that these cases, as presented by paranormalists, have ever really been established or actually represent the type of evidence the paranormalist presumes. As such, the need for this type of explanation becomes redundant. The theoretical divide then can be seen as one of sufficiency, where the paranormalist thinks a sufficient case has been made to demand explanation, and the neuroscientist views the case to be insufficient to warrant one."[30]

The "heightened lucid consciousness" of NDErs is according to Braithwaite[31] compatible with the predictions of the dying-brain hypothesis, "...the dying-brain hypothesis predicts that more vivid, profound, and meaningful NDEs are likely to be associated with greater degrees of disinhibition. Thus, NDEs reported when people truly are nearer to death (and hence the level of disinhibition would conceivably be greater), should be more vivid, profound, detailed and meaningful, relative to those reported when people only believed themselves to be so. This is exactly what has been found."

In contrast to the hypothesis that NDEs occur during the supposed period of no brain activity or brain activity insufficient to support consciousness, Braithwaite (2014), as well as psychologist Chris French[32] argued that the NDE could easily have occurred well before brain activity ceased, or well after during recovery. Parnia and Fenwick (2001) had rejected the idea that the NDE may have occurred just prior to or just after the loss of consciousness. They argued that LOC happens too quickly and that events that occur just prior (or just after) would not be expected to be recalled, and that the period of recovery is characterized by delirium and not by the lucid consciousness reported by NDErs. In a summary of these arguments, Braithwaite (2014) concluded that "all claims about the phenomenology being different between NDEs and syncope, or the time periods in cases of cardiac arrest being 'too quick' are irrelevant as neither pertain to the actual arguments from the syncopal model. As a consequence, these specific dualist arguments against syncope as a comparative model of NDEs can be legitimately ignored."

Parnia and Fenwick (2001) also argued that the occurrence of anecdotal reports of patients being able to see and recall detailed events occurring during the cardiac arrest that are afterwards verified by hospital staff supports the argument that such perception sometimes do occur during periods of clinical death. NDE researcher Janice Miner Holden found 107 such anecdotal reports in the NDE literature as of 2009, out of which approximately 91% were accurate.[33]

According to French (2005) and Blackmore (1993), when serious attempts at corroboration are attempted, the evidence often turns out to be nowhere near as impressive as it initially appeared.[34] And such cases can possibly (since they had not been ruled out) be accounted for in terms of non-paranormal factors including, "information available at the time, prior knowledge, fantasy or dreams, lucky guesses, and information from the remaining senses. Then there is selective memory for correct details, incorporation of details learned between the end of the NDE and giving an account of it, and the tendency to tell a good story.”[35]

NDE researchers have also been criticized by scientists of placing undue confidence in EEG measures. French (2005) and Braithwaite (2008, 2014) claimed that survivalists generally appear to assume that a flat EEG is indicative of total brain inactivity. Even assuming that NDEs actually occur during such periods, the assumption that isoelectric surface EEG recordings are always indicative of total brain inactivity is according to Braithwaite and French wrong. Braithwaite noted that "unless surgically implanted into the brain directly, the EEG principally measures surface cortical activity. The waveforms seen in cortical EEG are largely regarded to come from the synchronistic firing of cortical pyramidal neurons. As such, it is entirely conceivable that deep sub-cortical brain structures could be firing, and even in seizure, in the absence of any cortical signs of this activity."[36][37][38]

According to French (2005) future research in the near-death experience should focus on devising ways to distinguish between the two main hypotheses relating to when the NDE is occurring.[39] If it really is occurring when some NDE researchers claim that it is, during a period of flat EEG with no cortical activity, then modern neuroscience would require serious revision.[39] This would also be the case if the OBE, either within the NDE or not, could be shown to be veridical. Attempts to test the veridicality of OBEs using hidden targets (e.g., Parnia and Fenwick (2001) should be welcomed.[39]

See also

References

  1. ^ Kandel, ER; Schwartz JH; Jessell TM; Siegelbaum SA; Hudspeth AJ. "Principles of Neural Science, Fifth Edition" (2012).
  2. ^ Squire, L. et al. "Fundamental Neuroscience, 4th edition" (2012).
  3. ^ O. Carter Snead. "Neuroimaging and the "Complexity" of Capital Punishment" (2007).
  4. ^ Eric R. Kandel, M.D. "A New Intellectual Framework for Psychiatry" (1998).
  5. ^ "Neuroscience Core Concepts: The Essential Principles of Neuroscience". BrainFacts.org: Explore the Brain and Mind.
  6. ^ Farah, Martha J.; Murphy, Nancey (February 2009). "Neuroscience and the Soul". Science. 323 (5918): p. 1168. doi:10.1126/science.323.5918.1168a. Retrieved 20 November 2012. {{cite journal}}: |pages= has extra text (help)
  7. ^ Max Velmans, Susan Schneider. "The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness" (2008). p. 560.
  8. ^ Matt Carter, Jennifer C. Shieh. "Guide to Research Techniques in Neuroscience" (2009).
  9. ^ Aslihan Selimbeyoglu, Josef Parvizi. "Electrical stimulation of the human brain: perceptual and behavioral phenomena reported in the old and new literature" (2010). Frontiers in Human Neuroscience.
  10. ^ "Severe TBI Symptoms"
  11. ^ "Symptoms of Brain Injury"
  12. ^ "Cognitive Development and Aging: A Life Span Perspective"
  13. ^ "Adolescent Brains Are A Work In Progress"
  14. ^ "Blossoming brains"
  15. ^ "Brain death". Encyclopedia of Death and Dying. Retrieved 25 March 2014.
  16. ^ Young, G Bryan. "Diagnosis of brain death". UpToDate. Retrieved 25 March 2014.
  17. ^ Attention: This template ({{cite doi}}) is deprecated. To cite the publication identified by doi:10.4103/0972-5229.53108, please use {{cite journal}} (if it was published in a bona fide academic journal, otherwise {{cite report}} with |doi=10.4103/0972-5229.53108 instead.
  18. ^ Attention: This template ({{cite doi}}) is deprecated. To cite the publication identified by doi:10.4081/ni.2010.e2, please use {{cite journal}} (if it was published in a bona fide academic journal, otherwise {{cite report}} with |doi=10.4081/ni.2010.e2 instead.
  19. ^ Laureys, Steven; Tononi, Giulio. (2009). The Neurology of Consciousness: Cognitive Neuroscience and Neuropathology. Academic Press. p. 20. ISBN 978-0-12-374168-4
  20. ^ Piccinini, Gualtiero; Bahar, Sonya. "No Mental Life after Brain Death: The Argument from the Neural Localization of Mental Functions" (2011). University of Missouri - St. Louis.
  21. ^ Roberts, Glenn; Owen, John. (1988). The Near-Death Experience. British Journal of Psychiatry 153: 607-617.
  22. ^ Britton, Willoughby B. and Richard R. Bootzin. (2004). Near-Death Experiences and the Temporal Lobe. Psychological Science. Vol. 15, No. 4. pp. 254-258.
  23. ^ Linda J. Griffith. "Near-Death Experiences and Psychotherapy" (2009).
  24. ^ Mauro, James. Bright lights, big mystery. Psychology Today, July 1992
  25. ^ Vanhaudenhuyse, A; Thonnard, M; Laureys, S. "Towards a Neuro-scientific Explanation of Near-death Experiences?" (2009).
  26. ^ Olaf Blanke, Sebastian Dieguez. "Leaving Body and Life Behind: Out-of-Body and Near-Death Experience" (2009).
  27. ^ van Lommel P, van Wees R, Meyers V, Elfferich I. (2001) "Near-Death Experience in Survivors of Cardiac Arrest: A prospective Study in the Netherlands," The Lancet, December 15; 358 (9298):2039-45. Table 2.
  28. ^ Sam Parnia, Peter Fenwick. "Near death experiences in cardiac arrest: visions of a dying brain or visions of a new science of consciousness" (2001).
  29. ^ Greyson, B. (2003) Incidence and correlates of near-death experiences in a cardiac care unit. Gen. Hosp. Psychiat., 25: 269–276.
  30. ^ Dr. Jason J Braithwaite, Hayley Dewe MSc. "Occam's Chainsaw: Neuroscientific Nails in the Coffin of Dualist Notions of the Near-death Experience (NDE)" (2014).
  31. ^ Dr. Jason J Braithwaite. "Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of the Dying Brain" (2008).
  32. ^ French, Christopher C. "Near-death experiences in cardiac arrest survivors " (2005).
  33. ^ Holden, J.M. (2009) Veridical perception in near-death experiences. In The Handbook of Near-Death Experiences (Holden, J.M. et al., eds), pp. 185–211.
  34. ^ Blackmore, S.J. (1993) Dying to Live: Science and the Near-Death Experience. Grafton, London.
  35. ^ Blackmore, S.J. (1996b). Out-of-body experiences. In G. Stein (ed.), The encyclopedia of the paranormal. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. Pp. 471-483.
  36. ^ Cite error: The named reference Braithwaite 2008 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  37. ^ Paolin, A., Manuali, A., Di Paola, F., Boccaletto, F., Caputo, P., Zanata, R., Bardin, G.P. and Simini, G. (1995). Reliability in diagnosis of brain death. Intens Care Med 21: 657–662.
  38. ^ Bardy, A. H. (2002). Near-death experiences [letter]. Lancet 359: 2116.
  39. ^ a b c Cite error: The named reference French2005 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).

Further reading