Jump to content

Open-question argument: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
SmackBot (talk | contribs)
m →‎Notes and References: Correct cap in header and/or general fixes. using Project:AWB
Line 4: Line 4:


==Objections and rejoinders==
==Objections and rejoinders==
===''A Posteriori'' Identities===
===''A posteriori'' identities===


An important response to the open question argument by contemporary ethical naturalists (e.g., [[Peter Railton]]) is to understand a claim like "goodness is identical with pleasure" as an [[a posteriori]] identity claim on a par with "Water is H<sub>2</sub>O". The question "This is H<sub>2</sub>O but is it water?" is intelligible and so, in that limited sense, whether or not water is H<sub>2</sub>O is an open question, note that this does not address the issue of ''significance''. But that does not lead us to conclude that water is not H<sub>2</sub>O. "Water is H<sub>2</sub>O" is an identity claim that is known to be true ''[[a posteriori]]'' (i.e., it was discovered via empirical investigation). Another example is "redness" being identical to certain phenomena of electromagnetism. This is discovered by empirical investigation.
An important response to the open question argument by contemporary ethical naturalists (e.g., [[Peter Railton]]) is to understand a claim like "goodness is identical with pleasure" as an [[a posteriori]] identity claim on a par with "Water is H<sub>2</sub>O". The question "This is H<sub>2</sub>O but is it water?" is intelligible and so, in that limited sense, whether or not water is H<sub>2</sub>O is an open question, note that this does not address the issue of ''significance''. But that does not lead us to conclude that water is not H<sub>2</sub>O. "Water is H<sub>2</sub>O" is an identity claim that is known to be true ''[[a posteriori]]'' (i.e., it was discovered via empirical investigation). Another example is "redness" being identical to certain phenomena of electromagnetism. This is discovered by empirical investigation.
Line 12: Line 12:
A rebuttal to this is that trying to find an ''a posteriori'' means to learn what morality is, such as in the above example, run into the Open Question Argument all over again.<ref name="Ethical Theory p. 28"/> For example, it may be that we learn ''a posteriori'' that "redness" is identical to having certain electromagnetic properties, but ''first'' we must attach an initial, ''a priori'' definitional reference to the term "redness"--e.g. "that which produces the sensation 'red' to normal perceivers under standard conditions." Because the Open Question argument applies to all ''a priori'' statements of morality, it applies to the initial identity claim that "rightness" refers to "the property of acts, whatever it is, that is causally responsible for their tendency towards social stability."<ref>The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, by Hugh LaFollette (Editor), p. 30</ref> Whether rightness refers to that is an open question. The moral non-naturalist could argue that ''any'' attempt to make an initial identity reference for naturalistic morality is susceptible to the Open Question Argument.
A rebuttal to this is that trying to find an ''a posteriori'' means to learn what morality is, such as in the above example, run into the Open Question Argument all over again.<ref name="Ethical Theory p. 28"/> For example, it may be that we learn ''a posteriori'' that "redness" is identical to having certain electromagnetic properties, but ''first'' we must attach an initial, ''a priori'' definitional reference to the term "redness"--e.g. "that which produces the sensation 'red' to normal perceivers under standard conditions." Because the Open Question argument applies to all ''a priori'' statements of morality, it applies to the initial identity claim that "rightness" refers to "the property of acts, whatever it is, that is causally responsible for their tendency towards social stability."<ref>The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, by Hugh LaFollette (Editor), p. 30</ref> Whether rightness refers to that is an open question. The moral non-naturalist could argue that ''any'' attempt to make an initial identity reference for naturalistic morality is susceptible to the Open Question Argument.


===Analytic Equivalence===
===Analytic equivalence===


A moral naturalist could respond to the above claiming that "rightness" is analytically equivalent (essentially, true by definition, much as 2 + 2 is equivalent to 4) to "the property of acts that is causally responsible for social stability," even if this equivalency does not appear obvious.<ref>The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, by Hugh LaFollette (Editor), p. 31</ref> From there, both sides could dispute the plausibility of such equivalence statements being true by definition.
A moral naturalist could respond to the above claiming that "rightness" is analytically equivalent (essentially, true by definition, much as 2 + 2 is equivalent to 4) to "the property of acts that is causally responsible for social stability," even if this equivalency does not appear obvious.<ref>The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, by Hugh LaFollette (Editor), p. 31</ref> From there, both sides could dispute the plausibility of such equivalence statements being true by definition.


===Other Objections===
===Other objections===
Critics of Moore's arguments sometimes claim that he is appealing to general puzzles concerning analysis (cf. the [[paradox of analysis]]), rather than revealing anything special about value. Other responses appeal to the [[Frege]]an distinction between [[sense and reference]], allowing that value concepts are special and ''sui generis'', but insisting that value properties are nothing but natural properties (this strategy is similar to that taken by [[physicalism|non-reductive materialists]] in [[philosophy of mind]]).
Critics of Moore's arguments sometimes claim that he is appealing to general puzzles concerning analysis (cf. the [[paradox of analysis]]), rather than revealing anything special about value. Other responses appeal to the [[Frege]]an distinction between [[sense and reference]], allowing that value concepts are special and ''sui generis'', but insisting that value properties are nothing but natural properties (this strategy is similar to that taken by [[physicalism|non-reductive materialists]] in [[philosophy of mind]]).



Revision as of 02:17, 28 February 2010

The Open Question Argument is a philosophical argument put forward by the British philosopher G. E. Moore in §13 of Principia Ethica. The type of question Moore refers to in this argument is an identity question, "Is it true that X is Y?" Such a question is an open question if a conceptually competent speaker can question this, otherwise the question is closed. For example, "I know he doesn't eat meat but is he a vegetarian?" would be a closed question. However, "Is the morning star the same thing as the evening star?" is an open question; the question cannot be deduced from the conceptual terms alone. The Open Question Argument claims that any attempt to identify morality with some set of observable, natural properties will always be an open question (unlike, say, a horse, which can be defined in terms of observable properties). Moore further argued that if this is true, then moral facts cannot be reduced to natural properties, and that therefore ethical naturalism is false.

Objections and rejoinders

A posteriori identities

An important response to the open question argument by contemporary ethical naturalists (e.g., Peter Railton) is to understand a claim like "goodness is identical with pleasure" as an a posteriori identity claim on a par with "Water is H2O". The question "This is H2O but is it water?" is intelligible and so, in that limited sense, whether or not water is H2O is an open question, note that this does not address the issue of significance. But that does not lead us to conclude that water is not H2O. "Water is H2O" is an identity claim that is known to be true a posteriori (i.e., it was discovered via empirical investigation). Another example is "redness" being identical to certain phenomena of electromagnetism. This is discovered by empirical investigation.

Similarly, many moral naturalists argue that "rightness" being the property of "maximizing utility" is an a posteriori truth because we invoke rightness and wrongness to explain certain empirical phenomena, and then discover a posteriori that maximizing utility occupies the relevant explanatory role.[1] For example, they argue that since right actions contingently have certain effects e.g. being causally responsible for a tendency towards social stability—so it follows we can fix the term "right" refer to the empirical description "the property of acts, whatever it is, that is causally responsible for their tendency towards social stability."[1] With this description for "right," we can then investigate which acts accomplish this: e.g. those actions that maximize utility. We can then conclude that we have learned that "right" refers to "maximizing utility" through a posteriori means.

A rebuttal to this is that trying to find an a posteriori means to learn what morality is, such as in the above example, run into the Open Question Argument all over again.[1] For example, it may be that we learn a posteriori that "redness" is identical to having certain electromagnetic properties, but first we must attach an initial, a priori definitional reference to the term "redness"--e.g. "that which produces the sensation 'red' to normal perceivers under standard conditions." Because the Open Question argument applies to all a priori statements of morality, it applies to the initial identity claim that "rightness" refers to "the property of acts, whatever it is, that is causally responsible for their tendency towards social stability."[2] Whether rightness refers to that is an open question. The moral non-naturalist could argue that any attempt to make an initial identity reference for naturalistic morality is susceptible to the Open Question Argument.

Analytic equivalence

A moral naturalist could respond to the above claiming that "rightness" is analytically equivalent (essentially, true by definition, much as 2 + 2 is equivalent to 4) to "the property of acts that is causally responsible for social stability," even if this equivalency does not appear obvious.[3] From there, both sides could dispute the plausibility of such equivalence statements being true by definition.

Other objections

Critics of Moore's arguments sometimes claim that he is appealing to general puzzles concerning analysis (cf. the paradox of analysis), rather than revealing anything special about value. Other responses appeal to the Fregean distinction between sense and reference, allowing that value concepts are special and sui generis, but insisting that value properties are nothing but natural properties (this strategy is similar to that taken by non-reductive materialists in philosophy of mind).

Notes and references

  1. ^ a b c The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, by Hugh LaFollette (Editor), p. 28
  2. ^ The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, by Hugh LaFollette (Editor), p. 30
  3. ^ The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, by Hugh LaFollette (Editor), p. 31