Jump to content

Social intuitionism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
LeoRomero (talk | contribs)
rewrote lede, clarified/wikified terms, added citations, removed refimprove
Line 1: Line 1:
In [[moral psychology]], '''social intuitionism''' is a model that proposes that moral positions and judgments are: (1) primarily [[Intuition|intuitive]] ("intuitions come first"), (2) rationalized, justified, or otherwise explained after the fact, (3) taken mainly to influence other people, and are (4) often influenced and sometimes changed by discussing such positions with others.<ref>{{Cite book|title = The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion|last = Haidt|first = Jonathan|publisher = Pantheon|year = 2012|isbn = 978-0307377906|pages = 913 Kindle ed.}}</ref>
{{Refimprove|date=February 2009}}


In [[moral psychology]], '''social intuitionism''' proposes that moral judgments and actions are caused more by [[Intuition (knowledge)|intuition]] than by reason. It contradicts earlier, [[rationalist]] theories of morality, such as of [[Lawrence Kohlberg]]'s [[Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development|stage theory of moral reasoning]]. [[Jonathan Haidt]] (2001) greatly de-emphasizes the role of reasoning in reaching moral conclusions. Haidt asserts that moral judgment is primarily given rise to by [[Intuition (knowledge)|intuition]] with reasoning playing a very marginalized role in most of our moral decision-making. Conscious thought-processes serve as a kind of [[post hoc theorizing|post hoc]] justification of our decisions.
This model forks away from earlier [[rationalist]] theories of morality, such as of [[Lawrence Kohlberg]]'s [[Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development|stage theory of moral reasoning]].<ref>{{Cite journal|title = The Current Formulation of Kohlberg’s Theory and a Response to Critics|url = http://www.karger.com/doi/10.1159/000272945|journal = Human Development|pages = 94-100|volume = 28|issue = 2|doi = 10.1159/000272945|first = Charles|last = Levine|first2 = Lawrence|last2 = Kohlberg|first3 = Alexandra|last3 = Hewer}}</ref> [[Jonathan Haidt]] (2001) de-emphasizes the role of reasoning in reaching moral conclusions. Haidt asserts that moral judgment is primarily given rise to by [[Intuition (knowledge)|intuition]], with reasoning playing a smaller role in most of our moral decision-making. Conscious thought-processes serve as a kind of [[post hoc theorizing|post hoc]] justification of our decisions.


His main evidence comes from studies of "moral dumbfounding" where people have strong moral reactions but fail to establish any kind of rational principle to explain their reaction.<ref>Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012.</ref> An example situation in which moral intuitions are activated is as follows: Imagine that a brother and sister sleep together once. No one else knows, no harm befalls either one, and both feel it brought them closer as siblings. Most people imagining this [[incest]] scenario have very strong negative reaction, yet cannot explain why.<ref>Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012.</ref> Haidt suggests that we have intuitive [[heuristics]] which are unconscious<ref>Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012.</ref> that generate our reactions to morally charged situations and our moral behavior. He suggests that if people reason about morality, it is independent of processes causing moral decisions to be made.<ref>Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012.</ref>
His main evidence comes from studies of "moral dumbfounding" where people have strong moral reactions but fail to establish any kind of rational principle to explain their reaction.<ref>Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012. Loc 539, Kindle ed. In footnote 29, Haidt credits the neology of the term ''moral dumbfounding'' to social/experimental psychologist [[Daniel Wegner]]. </ref> An example situation in which moral intuitions are activated is as follows: Imagine that a brother and sister sleep together once. No one else knows, no harm befalls either one, and both feel it brought them closer as siblings. Most people imagining this [[incest]] scenario have very strong negative reaction, yet cannot explain why.<ref>Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012. Loc 763 Kindle ed.</ref> Referring to earlier studies by [[Howard Margolis]]<ref>{{Cite journal|title = Patterns, Thinking, and Cognition: A Theory of Judgment by Howard Margolis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987, 332 pp. (ISBN 0-226-50527-8)|url = http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00131728909335595|journal = The Educational Forum|date = 1989-06-30|issn = 0013-1725|pages = 199-202|volume = 53|issue = 2|doi = 10.1080/00131728909335595|first = Burton L.|last = Grover}}</ref> and others, Haidt suggests that we have [[Unconscious cognition|unconscious]] intuitive [[heuristics]] which generate our reactions to morally charged-situations, and underlie our moral behavior. He suggests that when people explain their moral positions, they often miss, if not hide, the core premises and processes that actually led to those conclusions.<ref>Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012. Loc 1160 Kindle ed.</ref>


Haidt's model also states that moral reasoning is more likely to be interpersonal than private, reflecting social motives rather than abstract principles. He does grant that interpersonal discussion (and, on very rare occasions, private reflection) can activate new intuitions which will then be carried forward into future judgments.
Haidt's model also states that moral reasoning is more likely to be interpersonal than private, reflecting social motives (reputation, alliance-building) rather than abstract principles. He does grant that interpersonal discussion (and, on very rare occasions, private reflection) can activate new intuitions which will then be carried forward into future judgments.


==Reasons to doubt the role of cognition==
==Reasons to doubt the role of cognition==

Revision as of 21:16, 20 November 2015

In moral psychology, social intuitionism is a model that proposes that moral positions and judgments are: (1) primarily intuitive ("intuitions come first"), (2) rationalized, justified, or otherwise explained after the fact, (3) taken mainly to influence other people, and are (4) often influenced and sometimes changed by discussing such positions with others.[1]

This model forks away from earlier rationalist theories of morality, such as of Lawrence Kohlberg's stage theory of moral reasoning.[2] Jonathan Haidt (2001) de-emphasizes the role of reasoning in reaching moral conclusions. Haidt asserts that moral judgment is primarily given rise to by intuition, with reasoning playing a smaller role in most of our moral decision-making. Conscious thought-processes serve as a kind of post hoc justification of our decisions.

His main evidence comes from studies of "moral dumbfounding" where people have strong moral reactions but fail to establish any kind of rational principle to explain their reaction.[3] An example situation in which moral intuitions are activated is as follows: Imagine that a brother and sister sleep together once. No one else knows, no harm befalls either one, and both feel it brought them closer as siblings. Most people imagining this incest scenario have very strong negative reaction, yet cannot explain why.[4] Referring to earlier studies by Howard Margolis[5] and others, Haidt suggests that we have unconscious intuitive heuristics which generate our reactions to morally charged-situations, and underlie our moral behavior. He suggests that when people explain their moral positions, they often miss, if not hide, the core premises and processes that actually led to those conclusions.[6]

Haidt's model also states that moral reasoning is more likely to be interpersonal than private, reflecting social motives (reputation, alliance-building) rather than abstract principles. He does grant that interpersonal discussion (and, on very rare occasions, private reflection) can activate new intuitions which will then be carried forward into future judgments.

Reasons to doubt the role of cognition

Haidt (2001) lists four reasons to doubt the cognitive primacy model championed by Kohlberg and others.[7]

  1. There is considerable evidence that many evaluations, including moral judgments, take place automatically, at least in their initial stages (and these initial judgments anchor subsequent judgments).
  2. The moral reasoning process is highly biased by two sets of motives, which Haidt labels "relatedness" motives (relating to managing impressions and having smooth interactions with others) and "coherence" motives (preserving a coherent identity and worldview).
  3. The reasoning process has repeatedly been shown to create convincing post hoc justifications for behavior that are believed by people despite not actually correctly describing the reason underlying the choice. This was demonstrated in a classic paper by Nisbett and Wilson (1977).
  4. According to Haidt, moral action covaries more with moral emotion than with moral reasoning.

Objections to Haidt's model

Joseph Paxton and Joshua Greene (2010) review evidence suggesting that moral reasoning plays a significant role in moral judgment, including counteracting automatic tendencies toward bias.[8] Greene and colleagues have proposed an alternative to the social intuitionist model suggesting that deontological moral judgments, which involve rights and duties, are driven primarily by intuition, while utilitarian judgments aimed at promoting the greater good are underlain by controlled cognitive reasoning processes.

References

  1. ^ Haidt, Jonathan (2012). The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion. Pantheon. pp. 913 Kindle ed. ISBN 978-0307377906.
  2. ^ Levine, Charles; Kohlberg, Lawrence; Hewer, Alexandra. "The Current Formulation of Kohlberg's Theory and a Response to Critics". Human Development. 28 (2): 94–100. doi:10.1159/000272945.
  3. ^ Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012. Loc 539, Kindle ed. In footnote 29, Haidt credits the neology of the term moral dumbfounding to social/experimental psychologist Daniel Wegner.
  4. ^ Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012. Loc 763 Kindle ed.
  5. ^ Grover, Burton L. (1989-06-30). "Patterns, Thinking, and Cognition: A Theory of Judgment by Howard Margolis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987, 332 pp. (ISBN 0-226-50527-8)". The Educational Forum. 53 (2): 199–202. doi:10.1080/00131728909335595. ISSN 0013-1725.
  6. ^ Haidt, Jonathan. The righteous mind. Pantheon: 2012. Loc 1160 Kindle ed.
  7. ^ Haidt, J. (2001). "The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment." Psychological Review, 108, 814-834.
  8. ^ Paxton, J., & Greene, J. (2010). "Moral reasoning: Hints and allegations." Topics in Cognitive Science, 2, 511-527.